Political Entrepreneurs

The Economic Engine of Political Change

The Problem With the Holdout Problem

March 28th, 2013 by Edward Lopez

In his famous 1979 lecture, “Politics Without Romance,” James M. Buchanan briefly summarizes public choice theory and some of its implications. He puts special emphasis on viewing government as made up of individuals who respond to incentives in the decisions they make. This is contrary to the naive view of government that was implicitly assumed before public choice came along. That naive view would go something like this: 1. identify a market failure (defined as voluntary exchange deviating from the ideal of Pareto optimality); and 2. justify government intervention to correct that market failure.  Buchanan calls this line of reasoning a “romantic” view of government, and he says it doesn’t hold up to even a little scrutiny.

It seems to be nothing more than simple and obvious wisdom to compare social institutions as they might be expected actually to operate rather than to compare romantic models of how such institutions might be hoped to operate.

Even so, the naive view presses on, as recent publications on the holdout problem demonstrate. The holdout problem arises when sellers of land (or other valuable resources) strategically choose not to sell, even though the would-be buyer offers a price that the seller would accept. Instead, the seller holds out for a higher price, and this might kill the deal or create delay costs. Strategic holdouts thereby prevent resources from flowing to more valued uses, which is termed inefficient in economics–that is, it’s a market failure. This line of argument is carefully developed in a 2011 paper in Public Choice, which promotes what Buchanan would call a romantic policy conclusion:

…the holdout problem arises in the presence of a supply-side externality and therefore justifies eminent domain (forced sale) to facilitate land assembly.

I have co-authored a new paper in response, titled “The Problem With the Holdout Problem” [free download on SSRN]. Here’s the upshot:

 The problem with the holdout problem is this: it is strictly a prima facie argument for justifying eminent domain, ignoring the potential for inefficiencies that may emerge when political authorities are empowered to substitute for market exchange. This is an old argument, articulated clearly in Buchanan (1962) and as early as Arthur Pigou in 1920.

In any [market failure], there is a prima facie case for public intervention. The case, however, cannot become more than a prima facie one, until we have considered the qualifications, which governmental agencies may be expected to possess for intervening advantageously. It is not sufficient to contrast the imperfect adjustments of unfettered private enterprise with the best adjustment that economists in their studies can imagine. For we cannot expect that any public authority will attain, or will even whole-heartedly seek, that ideal. Such authorities are liable alike to ignorance, to sectional pressure and to personal corruption by private interest.” (Pigou 1920, Pt.II, Ch.XX, Sec.4)

In the context of recent sequential bargaining models that identify strategic holdout as the proper justification for eminent domain, it bears scrutinizing whether regulators would use the takings power to correct for holdout inefficiencies and nothing more. We can imagine a benevolent and omniscient regulator who would choose “holdouts only,” thereby dissuading developers from incurring socially wasteful rent-seeking costs, and thus achieving the uniquely efficient outcome in Figure 2. However, as Buchanan and Pigou separately suggest, there is insight to be gained by relaxing the benevolence assumption. In this paper we assume that the regulator is instrumentally rational and fully informed. We find that the unrestricted regulator can have an incentive to use eminent domain on non-holdouts, and developers will thereby have the incentive to rent seek. These political actions generate two forms of social costs; therefore, the holdout justification of eminent domain is conditional…

[…]

In other words, eminent domain is justified on efficiency grounds if and only if the social costs of holdout exceed the combined social costs of rent seeking by the developer and externalities created by the regulator when using eminent domain on non-holdouts.

Enjoy. Again and again…

 

 

One thought on “The Problem With the Holdout Problem”

Comments are closed.

From the Pages of Madmen, Intellectuals, and Academic Scribblers (p.189, ch.7)

The most successful entrepreneurs know what they do well, they know the market and the opportunities within it, and they choose those activities that create the most value. This is true in economic as well as political markets.

From the Pages of Madmen, Intellectuals, and Academic Scribblers (p.178, ch.7)

[W]hen the right elements come together at the right time and place and overwhelm the status quo, it is because special people make it happen. We call them political entrepreneurs.

From the Pages of Madmen, Intellectuals, and Academic Scribblers (p.176. ch.7)

While we started this book with Danny Biasone saving basketball, we end it with Norman Borlaug saving a billion lives. These stories are not that different. Both faced vested interests, which were reinforced by popular beliefs that things should be a certain way—that is, until a better idea came along.

From the Pages of Madmen, Intellectuals, and Academic Scribblers (p.174, ch.6)

Because there was a general belief that homeownership was a good thing, politicians found the public with open arms.... Everybody was winning—except Alfred Marshall, whose supply and demand curves were difficult to see through the haze of excitement at the time, and except Friedrich Hayek, whose competition as a discovery procedure was befuddled... In short, once politicians started getting credit for homeownership rates, the housing market was doomed.

From the Pages of Madmen, Intellectuals, and Academic Scribblers (p.166, ch.6)

Everyone responded rationally to the incentives before them. In short, the rules that guided homeownership changed over time, which in turn changed the incentives of these actors. And bad things happened.

From the Pages of Madmen, Intellectuals, and Academic Scribblers (p.153, ch.6)

They understood the economics. The ideas had already won in ... the regulatory agency itself. All that remained to be overcome were some vested interests and a handful of madmen in authority.

From the Pages of Madmen, Intellectuals, and Academic Scribblers (p.146, ch.6)

If the idea for auctions of spectrum use rights had been part of the public debate since at least 1959, why didn’t the relevant institutions change sooner? What interests stood in the way?

From the Pages of Madmen, Intellectuals, and Academic Scribblers (p.121, ch.5)

When an academic scribbler comes up with a new idea, it has to resonate well with widely shared beliefs, which in turn must overcome the vested interests at the table. Many forces come together to explain political change, even though it may seem like coincidence of time and place.

From the Pages of Madmen, Intellectuals, and Academic Scribblers (p.120, ch.5)

It’s the rules of the political game that deserve our focus, not politicians’ personalities or party affiliations.

From the Pages of Madmen, Intellectuals, and Academic Scribblers (p.119, ch.5)

In short, ideas are a type of higher-order capital in society. Like a society that is poor in capital and therefore produces little consumer value, a society that is poor in ideas and institutions will have bad incentives and therefore few of the desirable outcomes that people want.

©2024 Wayne A Leighton & Edward López • Web Design by Barrel Strength